The Struggle for Recognition
Identities are controlling systems
which alter and shape our everyday behaviour. In Francis Fukuyama’s new book,
identities are not biologically determined, but constructed out of complex
political processes (p. 122). Importantly, identities are multiple – that is,
we embody different identities according to the social/political contexts we
find ourselves in. Fukuyama explores the role of identity in today’s political
world. The demands of identity, he claims, govern world politics.
Fukuyama’s treatment of identity is
not so much sociological as it is political. The clear aim of his book is to
provide a useful framework for a wide range of current issues, ranging from
Brexit to politicised Islam.
© Stanford University |
Fukuyama begins by analysing the part
played by a basic human need. Drawing on Plato’s ideas of the soul, Fukuyama
argues that it is human nature to demand equal recognition. Fukuyama’s platonic
term is thymos – the craving for ‘positive
judgements about [one’s] worth or dignity’ (p. 18). Accordingly, thymos ‘is the seat of today’s identity
politics’. Thymos is important
because today’s liberal democracies recognise, or assert, that ‘everyone [is] inherently
equal’ (p. 22) and the demand for recognition is widespread. However, thymos has spilled into the national
sphere and transitioned into a power play of nations that demand recognition
for their superiority. Today’s problems arise from dissonant political voices.
Fukuyama presents the reader with a
short history of ideas to explain the creation of modern understandings of
identity. He argues that identity began 500 years ago with the Lutheran
Reformation. Martin Luther, an Augustinian friar, gave birth to the Western
notion of individual identity. He focused on the individual believer rather
than the prevailing ‘social structures’ of the Mediaeval Church (p. 27). But
this idea developed with the thinking of later European philosophers. Jean Jacques
Rousseau, for instance, emphasised the individual will against ‘outer society’
(p. 33). In the nineteenth-century, Friedrich Hegel viewed humans as free moral agents ‘who
are simply rational machines seeking to maximise satisfaction of their desires' (p. 39). Today, Fukuyama says, dignity of the inner self rests on the idea of moral
freedom (p. 40). Thus, modern identity politics which focus on the lived
experience of individuals, such as feminism, and their demand for equal recognition
grew out of a long history of twists and developments in how philosophers and
critical thinkers viewed human beings (p. 110).
Fukuyama’s account gives prominence to
the rise of nationalism since the late eighteenth-century. Nation building is,
at heart, a divisive project that makes and breaks identities. It depends on ‘stories
of peoplehood’ manufactured by all levels of society: including artists, elites,
historians, and ordinary people (p. 142). National identities have depended on
such inclusive (and exclusive) concepts like race, ethnicity, and shared language
(pp 140-41). Nations created citizenship, a concept which became more important
after the 1990s as immigration rose and put national identity into question.
Citizenship, Fukuyama says, is a two-way street which endows ‘citizens with
rights that are protected by the state, but it also enjoins duties on them,
above all, the duty of loyalty to the country’s principles and laws’ (p. 148).
Yet identity problematises citizenship in the contemporary world. For instance,
one’s identity values may not necessarily match with the values of the state.
In such a world, Fukuyama provides some solutions.
For liberal democracies to be more
functional, we need to seek further common ground in the shape of shared principles
and virtues. Multiple identities are an inevitable part of the societies we
live in – therefore we need to practice empathy and dignity, and also agree
upon a shared code of values and aspirations within the nations we live in. We
need to look at the broader picture, promoting ‘creedal national identities
built around the foundational ideas of modern liberal democracy’ (p. 166).
In the face of overwhelming
immigration from the East into Europe, liberal democracies need to ensure new
citizens feel committed to national values. Fukuyama proposes the ‘universal
requirement for national service’ (p. 174). Such a view would stamp down on problems
like, say, politicised Islam by overtly showing that liberal democracies refuse
to tolerate radical actions contrary to their national values. As such
[i]f such service was
correctly structured, it would force young people to work together with others
from very different social classes, regions, races, and ethnicities, just as
military service does today (p. 174).
Unquestionably, liberal democracies
have the right to control their borders, hence they should have the same right
to test new citizens on the acceptance of their nation's values systems (pp 174-75).
In a world filled with various
identities, recognition drives political actions. The solution is to acknowledge
identities and also refuse to give credit where it is not due. Identities are
valuable if they contribute to a better world. Valorisation of collective identities
thus depends on their value to everyone, not to a select few. Fukuyama’s rich
understanding of current affairs offers a simple yet complex solution to today’s
political decay. His advice is valuable and thought provoking.
Source:
Identity:
Contemporary Identity Politics and the Struggle for Recognition. By Francis Fukuyama. Profile Books:
London, 2018. Pp xvii + 218 incl. 2 Tables. £16.99. 978-1-78125-9801.
Comments
Post a Comment